Message-Id: <199805092308.TAA70438@h-net.msu.edu>
Date: Sat, 9 May 1998 16:07:55 -0700
Sender: H-Net list for Asian History and Culture
<H-ASIA@h-net.msu.edu>
From: Frank Conlon <conlon@u.washington.edu>
Subject: H-ASIA: Review Dowling on Friedman,_Politics of
Democratization_
To: H-ASIA@H-NET.MSU.EDU
Edward Friedman, ed. _The Politics of Democratization: Generalizing East Asian Experiences_. Transitions: Asia and Asian America Series. Boulder and Oxford: Westview Press, 1994. xi + 276 pp. Contributors' list, bibliographical references, and index. $23.95 (paper), ISBN 0-8133-2265-0.
This book is one of a series, the editor of which is Mark Selden,
whose distinction between issues of 'pure' versus policy-oriented
research
(with his shuddered rejection of the very concept of pure
research) may hint at what we are to expect from the present authors.
And indeed what they offer is (to quote Jeanne Kirkpatrick) the
popular American conviction that it is possible to democratize
governments, any time, anywhere, under any circumstances.
[1]
Section I of this review gives a summary survey of selected parts of the work, comment is in Section II.
The book's editor, Edward Friedman, takes the lion's share of this book with over sixty pages which aim to give a frame of reference in which to place the other contributors. They are Masanori Nakamura, David Arase, and Yasunobu Sato on Japan (54 pp.); Tun-jen Cheng and Eun Mee Kim, and Heng Lee on Korea (33 pp.); Ming K. Chan on Hong Kong (20 pp.); Hung-mao Tien and Hsin-Huang Michael Hsiao on Taiwan (33 pp.); and Su Shaozhi and Stephen Manning on China (27 pp.).
In his Introduction and Theoretical Overview
(which has the
same title as the book), Friedman seems to conceive democracy as a
state in which accountable governments are institutionally and
peacefully chosen without fear
and by fair rules
to
deliver a transparent administration. I think he also regards
judiciary independence, due process of law, and human and civil
rights
as of the essence of democracy (p. 3), but since he doesn't
clearly distinguish democracy itself from either its pre-conditions
(if any) or its outcomes, I may be wrong.
I may be wrong because, in his Introduction, Friedman repeatedly
emphasises that in his view, there are _no_ unique historical,
cultural, and class preconditions
for democracy (p. 4), and
there's nothing in Europe or the West that was peculiarly conducive to
democracy. What _does_ lead to democracy says Friedman, is politics.
Politics themselves, however (the _only_ preconditions
of
democracy) have no preconditions at all; for politics lie in a
contingent realm
(p. 41). Rather than focusing on inherited
historical preconditions,
he writes,
the universal political approach of the authors investigate political actions, leadership, alliances, programs, trade-offs, and the like. Democratization is then understood as the building of political institutions, common interests, and new forms of legitimation. Consolidating a democracy requires building political parties and alliances capable of establishing credible national agendas and control of the military, making the security forces accountable to electoral representatives, and crafting a constitutional arrangement ... that will seem fair, open, and in the interests of all major social sectors, including old and new elites. (p. 5)There's nothing at all distinctive about the West's democratic achievements. Anyone can do it, anywhere, any time:
In contrast to the lesson derived from theories premised on unique historical, cultural and class preconditions that people must wait for democracy ... the lesson from a focus on ordinary politics in Japan or anywhere is that democrats can learn and then act more wisely in the here and now to secure democracy(p. 4). What is needed for democracy is not
unique preconditionsbut
generalizable politics,for
[d]emocracy in the West was not the consequence of a purported culture of Protestant individualist consciences(p. 7). All of which is illustrated, according to Friedman, by his contributing authors. History has shown that
uniqueculture has nothing at all to contribute to democracy: to the contrary,
democratic cultures are the consequences, not the causes, of democratization(p. 20). Although Friedman nowhere elaborates a definition of democracy, he regards its definition as of such impact that influential and
narrowly self-servingEurocentric theorists with their
[h]istorical cultural blindershave so grievously _misdefined_ democracy as actually to conclude that Japan is not a democracy at all:
[i]n this view that mythologizes the Western experience, democracy means a clash of opposing interests resulting in the voting of 'ins' out of power. Democracy is defined so that Japan is not democratic(p. 19).
Friedman regards this as misconceived since, by his criteria, Japan
_is_ democratic. Those criteria are given on page 21: 1) fair rules,
2) the possibility of peaceful challenge to existing rule, 3) the
possibility of eventual compromise between government and opposition.
In less than two pages (pp. 22-23) Friedman summarises the
U.S.-Japanese reaction to the Cold War to serve as an example of _how_
Japan then consolidated
its democracy.
If I properly grasp him here, he claims that Japanese democracy was
consolidated during that period because (and only because) Japan's
socialists succeeded in preventing Japan from military action on
the side of U.S. Cold War policies. The socialists won on this agenda
because ... the ruling Yoshida faction and bureaucrats of the powerful
Ministry of Finance were willing to forego a global politico-military
role for Japan.
The resultant compromise, diagnostic of democratic
consolidation, was itself the result of the government's
concessions to left-wing challengers
(p. 23),_i.e._, the result
of party politics. Such political compromise in Japan did in fact
reveal a general political pattern for the consolidation of
democracy
which, in the case in question, had nothing to do with
any cultural or historical disposition to social harmony. It was
contemporary politics, not historical culture.
The post-WW II outcome in Japan was a grand conservative coalition,
usually treated by Western analysts as so strange as to be beyond the
pale of democratic mores ...
(p. 46). He calls it a coalition, I
think, not because the conservatives formed a coalition of parties or
factions but rather because, as I understand him, the LDP formed a _de
facto_ coalition with the socialists to isolate the extremes of the
left and right. There is a hint of a suggestion, on page 47, that
Japan's grand conservative coalition
(an oft-repeated phrase)
actually constituted a _socialist_ victory since, had the established
middle and upper classes been isolated, they'd have been strong enough
to stop any democratic consolidation. (He thinks the same happened in
England in and after 1688, and in America's Federalist success.)
Friedman concludes that [t]o understand democratization, it is
useful to abandon a misleading opposition of consensual Asia versus
individualistic Europe and to rethink Western experience in terms of
generalizable lessons of consensus building
(p. 25).
Briskly moving from Japan in the Cold War to China's history from
Confucius to the present day (pp. 24 ff.) Friedman suggests that Deng
Xiaoping was much mistaken not to have foreseen that his 1989
suppression of democratic forces
would lose him a place in which
his name and fame would resound happily to Chinese ears for
centuries to come
(p. 25). And an equally curt glance at Mencian
Confucianism's doctrine of popular support as the only basis for
legitimate rule, and Confucius's concept of the educability of
everyman, and Daoism's focus of freedom, the Legalists' concept of
universal equality before the law, and Mohism on egalitarianism and
the yin-yang school on compromise and dialogue ... [shows that]
China seems replete with tendencies favorable to democratization
(pp. 27-8).
Friedman actually says, on page 28, that in the light of the foregoing
[o]ne might expect that Chinese _culture_ [my italics] ... would
lead Chinese intellectuals ... to take the lead against
... Leninism
; and, he adds, [t]hat is precisely what happened
in China's 1989 democracy movement
(p. 28). He therefore feels
able to conclude that all [_sic_] people and all [_sic_] cultures
are alive with a democratic potential.
However, on page 31, having said that [a]ny society tends to be
rich in multiple possibilities,
he immediately and in the next
sentence adds that in actuality, most cultures are largely
authoritarian.
Whence I infer that his position, if coherent, is a
intricate as these words suggest.
He repeatedly asserts or implies that democracy is a good thing. It
has always been the simple truth that democracy was humanly
attractive and dictatorship inhumanly repellent
(p. 33), and
the universal attractiveness of democracy and human rights
(p.
34) should need no demonstration.
But lest they do, he gives such demonstration, saying that democracy
can appeal to any society because democracy helps bar the evils of
a permanent succession crisis that, in despotisms, continually
threatens chaos;
it offers public accountability that can limit
... corruption;
and blocks arbitrary arrest, degrading
treatment, internal exile, slaughter,and torture ... Whether the
culture values face, pride, or individual dignity, only political
freedom can offer a life fit for human beings
(p. 34), for such
freedom is a facilitator of continuous progress
(p. 35).
Yet, alas, the universal appeal of these obvious truths _was_
concealed from Marx, Weber, _et al._, who slight the East Asian
experience that the authors of this volume stress, moral legitimacy,
the politics of social equity, and democratic consensus building
(p. 35).
Friedman considers the widely held view that first, since it was individualism in the West which led to its democratic achievements and, secondly, since such individualism is lacking in East Asia, therefore East Asia will have difficulty in developing democracy. On page 36, he simply denies the two premises, and claims that the observable fact of successful East Asian democracies prompts reassessment:
In the conventional wisdom, democracy in Europe is related to a rise of self-interested individuals. In East Asia, successful democracy is linked to the rise of a patriotic people willing a common, better destiny. _But that is how it actually was in the West, too._ The East Asian experience calls attention to almost buried Western essentials. Democracy succeeds best when it ends archaic humiliations imposed on a long-suffering people. Even when one looks at the revolutions of 1688, 1776, and 1789, one finds in England, America, and France, as in East Asia, an emerging group solidarity that defined the old despotic system as outmoded, traitorous, and beyond the pale of the true national community. To look back at Western experience with a vision sharpened by East Asian glasses focused on nationalistic identities permits one to see both East and West more clearly ... The East Asian experience thus permits the uncovering and recovering of the West's actual political path to democracy. [my italics]In this connexion he considers Japan (p. 37f.):
National survival required political democracy and social equity ... In Japan, the democratic constitution, social equity, land reform, and legalization of labor unions facilitated a prodemocracy consciousness ... [W]ithin a democratic consensus, conservatives, needing a regular popular mandate, offered the Shinto-Buddhist-Confucian people of Japan a social equity pact that could facilitate national consensus [for] ...[c]ommon identity does [!] matter. Democracy is not easy to consolidate in a nation-state era if there is no shared national identity ... [and] the conventional wisdom that dismisses East Asia because people there are supposedly homogeneous could not be more wrong. It is _wrong everywhere_ because, when closely examined, _all_ constructed national identities are replete with an almost endless diversity of particularisms from histories of conquest, sectarian religious conversions, regional affections, and speech differences ... In the chapters on democratization in Taiwan and Korea the authors correct the error of dismissing East Asia's achievement with the misleading assertion that it is uniquely homogeneous.
That surely is not how the feudatories of Tokugawa Japan conceived each other. A politics replete with regionalisms, particularisms, and conflicting interest is _ubiquitous_. ... That divisive danger was softened during democratization in Japan, Taiwan, and Korea because of political mobilization against a common threat to all in the nation and because of governmental policies fostering greater equity among diverse social groups. Politics can encourage local communalisms to find a fair stake in a national democratic community, a compacted patriotism [my italics]
Contrary to the Occidentalism
of self-serving
and
blinkered
Eurocentrics that there is something culturally
peculiar about the West,
the West is not that different from the
East for, as in the East, democracy is also under threat in the West,
where
[r]eligious or _cultural_fundamentalism, racist nativism, and military chauvinism still threaten democracy. As with those French forces backing fascism in the Nazi era, as with the racism that facilitated America's civil war, as with the embrace of local ethnonationalisms against the United Kingdom, political threats to democratic consolidation persist ... _The politicization of ethnic, regional, religious, and other cultural identities can challenge democracy anywhere_. (pp. 38f, my ital.).Such Eurocentric Occidentalism is also invoked by Orientalist Asian
dictators to legitimate their anti-democratic cause by contending that their people are not yet ready for democracy,as did the old French counter-revolutionary monarchists. Such
super patriotsas
Korean reactionaries, Taiwan militarists, or Mainland Chinese xenophobesalso pretend that democratic movements will cause national disintegration. They claim that Western
individualismis
hostile to virtually all _cultural_ communitieswhereas, in fact,
the actual creation of national culture in the democratizing West was also in conflict with the West's subsequent mythos of rational secular individualism(p. 40 my ital.).
Democracy was first said to be confined to Calvinists, then to all Protestants, then to all Christians:
But by the end of the twentieth century, after lengthy eras of democracy in Hindu-Muslim-Sikh-Buddhist India and Shinto-Buddhist-Confucian Japan and its spread to Confucian East Asians, Muslim Albanians, animistic Pacific Islanders, and Buddhist Mongols, one might think that this diversity would discredit all notions of peculiar cultural, value or socioeconomic prerequisites of democracy (p. 40).Friedman, however, still allows some connexion between the economy and democracy. While on page 2 he rejects the
conventional wisdomthat
a large middle-class socioeconomic foundationis a
preconditionof democracy (repeated on p. 12 and 32), he also says, on page 33, that economic growth can
helpdemocratization. And on page 51 he remarks that
Japan's grand conservative coalition actually has much to teach about ... a linkage of a legitimate polity to economic growth.However he immediately, on the same page, claims that in Chile and Taiwan
democratization was made possible not by economic growth but by political struggles,and that
[p]olitics ... is not an immediate reflection of some deeper economic reality. Democracy is not determined by economic preconditions.
That last quoted sentence seems contradicted by Masanoru Nakamura on
page 70 of his following contribution, Democratization, Peace, and
Development in Occupied Japan.
His main concern is with the
politics and economics of the Reverse Course and the Dodge Line. He
believes that economic stability and growth could encourage both
labor and business to abide by the rules of a democratic political
process
(p. 69). And epitomises the relation between politics
and economics by saying that
The Japanese experience after the occupation reveals _mutual_
support between democracy and development. The
democratization of economic reward was only delayed, not
denied. In the era of high-speed economic growth, movements
for wage increases, social welfare, and social security
policies were institututionalized. In contrast, in the
post-oil shock years when economic growth was sluggish, people
tended toward conservatism, and the movement for further
democratic progress receded. (p. 70, my ital.)
That passage, which continues his identification, on page 62, of
democracy with progressivism
and of conservatism with
anti-democracy, also continues his claim that there are indeed
economic and ideological mainstays
for political structures
(p. 64).
David Arase's chapter, on Japan's Foreign Policy and Asian
Democratization,
explores Japan's shift from the Yoshida
doctrine
of low-cost, low-risk
dependency on America to an
independent international influence consistent with its economic
power. Japan, without being selfish or crudely interventionist,
can link its resources to the promotion of democracy and human rights
in the countries of democratizing Asia ... [but] has not grasped the
opportunity to lead Asia toward democracy despite the many gains and
modest costs involved, due to domestic factors
(pp. 83 and 96).
The _reason_ for this woeful dereliction is obvious to Arase:
The insulated, autonomous bureaucracy serving primarily the interest of the dominant conservative coalition keeps Japan from embracing democracy in foreign policy. This gap can hurt Japan's search for an appropriate set of values that are classically 'political,' that is, having to do with defining those moral and spiritual values that accompany the good life not just for Japanese but for all of humanity (p. 97).In this connexion he is particularly severe on Motofumi Asai's claim that
the true nature of the Tiananmen incident is unclear,since the participants
interpreted democracy as all democrats do, and no one credits the Li Peng government's account of the massacre, of peaceable soldiers responding to violent attacks by hoodlums(p. 91).
As with Friedman, Arase offers no extended examination of the nature of democracy, or of what he takes democracy to be, although at one point he explicitly recognises the possibility of a different view from that presupposed by Friedman:
... Ardath Burks notes that Japanese democracy 'opts in favour of the individual person rather than for individualism. The person often achieves security in the group. ... To the Japanese, it is the right to belong to a group and to become involved in a demanding but protective world of duties that is the core of human rights.' _Equating democracy with individualism may be problematic._ Nevertheless, calls for human rights and government accountability are compatible with _all_ Asian systems and portend continued democratic development in ways suitable to these Asian societies (p. 96, my ital.)Yasunobu Sato's
New directions in Japanese foreign policy ...considers the Tiananmen incident, Japanese promotion of human rights and democracy in Asia, and ODA. His consideration of these topics is little (if anything) more than a repetition of standard and well-known slightly left of center critics such as Asia Watch, Amnesty International, _et al._.
I am sorry to ignore the contributions on Hong Kong, Korea, Taiwan and China, but this review is already far too long.
Stephen Manning's final contribution, however, merits attention because of its apparent inconsistency with the over-all Friedmanian orientation of the book.
Manning does echo Friedman's lamentations about the Eurocentric
and self-congratulatory
thesis that posits democratization
as a historically specific phenomenon
etc..
But he then considers the social and the cultural
conditions
(or preconditions
) of democracy (pp. 232-3) and concludes that
[s]ocial pluralism, that is, the existence of a variety of groups
that are independent of the state, is conducive to, indeed a crucial
precondition for, democratic development ...
(p.233). He thinks
that has been demonstrably so in China so that the obstacle to
democratizing therefore seems to Chinese analysts to be not in
economics but in social values. Democracy requires a transvaluation
of social values. (p.238)
Such a shift in mind-set is perhaps a
first and necessary step in the eventual emergence of a genuine civil
society (_loc. cit._).
The same, however, cannot be said for that beteist of the _bete noir_, culture, where he centers on the Beast with seven heads and ten horns, the apocalyptic Huntington, whom he rebuts by appeal to Barrington Moore _et al._.
In his conclusion he briefly mentions six additional explanatory
variables [which] together can comprise a composite theory of
democratization.
They are foreign relations, economic development,
economic growth-rate, income distribution, international debt, and the
economic system type. Of these eight environment variables, only
two---a market-oriented economic system and an independent and
autonomous civil society---correlate strongly with a democratic
transition
(p.243). Politics is in the drivers seat but [t]his
is not to urge unidimensionality, and ignore other, non-political
variables
(p.244)---all of which seems inconsistent with Friedman.
I think most political theorists distinguish, albeit intuitively, between matters of political fact on the one hand and, on the other, concepts used in the description of those facts; between empirical political science and political philosophy. It's often hard to decide where one ends and the other begins but, at least ideally, the distinction (even when made only to be rejected) is tolerably familiar.
I think it's also fair to claim that there is a large class of terms,
of which democracy
is one, which are _essentially_ ambiguous,
or contestable. However, lest I be seen as idiosyncratically
question-begging, let me quote A.W. Sparkes's _Talking Politics: A
Wordbook_:
It is not news that the words 'democracy', 'democratic',
'democrat' are both ambiguous and vague, that they have
'emotive force' and all the rest of it. As Hobbes might say,
many apply the word 'democratic' to any socio-political thing
_liked_, merely because they like it ... What is undemocratic
is the socio-political _misliked_ (p. 148)
This kind of talk,
claims Sparkes, has nothing to recommend
it
which, if not new, seems (if one might venture) true.
I am therefore bound to note as a massive weakness of these essays the
failure to grasp what Sparkes thought to be elementary. Thus we find
Arase saying that the Tiananmen participants interpreted democracy
as all democrats do
(p. 91). _All democrats_ interpret democracy
the same way? I'd not have thought it needed a Sparkes to tell us the
assumption is indefensible. But there it is.
While Arase's remark is the _locus classicus_ of this weakness, the same weakness does rather run through the whole book, and I'll concentrate my attention on it.
Nothing in this book would suggest that it's perfectly well-known that
the concept of natural rights
(the old-fashioned term for
human rights
) was rejected by Burke, Hume, Hegel, Bentham,
Mill, Marx and (by implication) Austin and Wittgenstein. Bentham, it
is notorious, dismissed the concept as nonsense.
These
philosophers may have been mistaken (for some sort of
transcendental deduction
may be conceivable) but it seems
reckless to develop a whole argument as though they'd never spoken.
And that seems even less defensible when, as I believe, virtually
everything that most believers in human rights want to claim can
equally be claimed without any reference whatever to these fictions.
The only loss (I assume) will be that of a spurious sanction, for it
may sound grander (to the uncritical), more persuasive (to the many)
to say everybody has a human right to liberty
than to say I,
Eric Dowling, would like everybody to be free if that were
possible.
While its not in place here to argue the case against the concept of human rights, it is in order to suggest that it not be taken for granted in the way that these authors have, particularly since they use the term so extensively in their references to other central concepts, like democracy.
Friedman's enthusiasm for the virtues of democracy, its simple
truth
and universal attractiveness,
(obvious to everyone of
sound mind and honest disposition) is reminiscent of the earlier
Western enthusiasm for the virtues of Christianity, similarly obvious
and ready for export to the benighted heathen. And when Asian leaders
fail to share that enthusiasm they are traduced as dishonestly seeking
to legitimate their anti-democratic cause
etc. But I can't see
that this enthusiasm for democracy is any less Eurocentric
than
Christianity was, nor any more obvious in its virtues. Friedman seems
to assume that it is _perfectly_ obvious that the future could hold
nothing better than democracy. He may, however, be mistaken: it's not
impossible. Enthusiasm is no substitute for analysis and
demonstration.
Neither is it obvious that the concept of Asian values
is, for
all its confusion, wholly without merit. Friedman speaks of the
error of ... the misleading assertion that it [East Asia] is uniquely
homogeneous. That surely is not how the feudatories of Tokugawa Japan
conceived each other. A politics replete with regionalisms,
particularisms, and conflicting interest is _ubiquitous_.
All of
which seems to me a gross over-simplification, unfortunately very
common and thoroughly confusing.
Here I may refer to a discussion in The Dead Fukuzawa Society between
T.J. Pempel and Brian McVeigh on 27 and 28 May 1997 on the topic of
homogenized Japan,
in which McVeigh pushed the Friedman line.
Pempel simply invited comparison of Japan with Switzerland (on
cultural homogeneity), U.S. (on ethnic sub-grouping), Australia (on
immigrant sub-grouping) and concluded a longish rejoinder by inviting
McVeigh to compare the various public opinion surveys done among
citizens of the OECD; Japanese almost invariably come up with far less
deviation from the national mean than do most other countries ... Do
Japanese differ on their answers? Sure; but far less than the
Americans, the Italians, or Belgians. You want to stress, it seems,
that 'Japanese differ from on another.' I don't disagree; I suggest
that these differences are, generally, far less than in numerous other
countries.
While it does seem to me that Pempel is right and
Friedman and McVeigh are wrong, what is even more obvious is that what
Friedman takes to be obvious is obviously not obvious.
To come to Arase's remark, quoted above, that Ardath Burks noted that
for the Japanese The person often achieves security in the
group. ... To the Japanese, it is the right to belong to a group and
to become involved in a demanding but protective world of duties that
is the core of human rights.
(Rikki Kersten elaborates a little on
this in her _Democracy in Post-war Japan: Maruyama Masao and the
Search for Autonomy,_ p. 213.) Arase agrees with Kersten when he
comments that _[e]quating democracy with individualism may be
problematic,_ and his unease is understandable, since he thinks that
all democrats interpret democracy the same way.
It is therefore most unfortunate that Arase and Friedman failed to see the full significance of Burks's remarks, not merely for their understanding of Japanese politics, but also for their understanding of the concepts of democracy and consensus.
Finally, I should note that Friedman's concept of democracy as
essentially incorporating fair rules
is not all that obviously
consistent with his belief that Japan is a democracy. For it hasn't
seemed that obvious to the many critics who have noted its judiciary
as _typically_ refusing to accept the most obvious of implied
rights (when claimed against the state), as preferring (unlike the
democratic High Court of Australia) to leave legislation to the
democratically elected legislators. Which rather suggests that the
conceptual analysis of democracy
is more complex than these
authors have presupposed.
[1]. See Selden's introduction to a symposium Asia, Asian Studies,
and the National Security State
in _The Bulletin of Concerned
Asian Scholars_, Jan.-March 1997 and Jeanne Kirkpatrick, as quoted by
D. K. Mauzy in The human rights and Asian values debate in
Southeast Asia ... ,
_Pacific Rev_., 10:2, 1997, p. 214.